翻訳と辞書
Words near each other
・ Proboszczewice
・ Proboszczowice, Silesian Voivodeship
・ Proboszczowice, Łódź Voivodeship
・ Proboszczów
・ Probot
・ Probota
・ Probota Monastery
・ Probota River (Bahluieț)
・ Problem of Apollonius
・ Problem of evil
・ Problem of evil in Hinduism
・ Problem of future contingents
・ Problem of Hell
・ Problem of induction
・ Problem of mental causation
Problem of multiple generality
・ Problem of other minds
・ Problem of pain
・ Problem of points
・ Problem of religious language
・ Problem of the criterion
・ Problem of time
・ Problem of universals
・ Problem picture
・ Problem play
・ Problem property
・ Problem set
・ Problem shaping
・ Problem Solved
・ Problem solving


Dictionary Lists
翻訳と辞書 辞書検索 [ 開発暫定版 ]
スポンサード リンク

Problem of multiple generality : ウィキペディア英語版
Problem of multiple generality
The problem of multiple generality names a failure in traditional logic to describe certain intuitively valid inferences. For example, it is intuitively clear that if:
:''Some cat is feared by every mouse''
then it follows logically that:
:''All mice are afraid of at least one cat''
The syntax of traditional logic (TL) permits exactly four sentence types: "All As are Bs", "No As are Bs", "Some As are Bs" and "Some As are not Bs". Each type is a quantified sentence containing exactly one quantifier. Since the sentences above each contain two quantifiers ('some' and 'every' in the first sentence and 'all' and 'at least one' in the second sentence), they cannot be adequately represented in TL. The best TL can do is to incorporate the second quantifier from each sentence into the second term, thus rendering the artificial-sounding terms 'feared-by-every-mouse' and 'afraid-of-at-least-one-cat'. This in effect "buries" these quantifiers, which are essential to the inference's validity, within the hyphenated terms. Hence the sentence "Some cat is feared by every mouse" is allotted the same logical form as the sentence "Some cat is hungry". And so the logical form in TL is:
:''Some As are Bs''
:''All Cs are Ds''
which is clearly invalid.
The first logical calculus capable of dealing with such inferences was Gottlob Frege's ''Begriffsschrift'' (1879), the ancestor of modern predicate logic, which dealt with quantifiers by means of variable bindings. Modestly, Frege did not argue that his logic was more expressive than extant logical calculi, but commentators on Frege's logic regard this as one of his key achievements.
Using modern predicate calculus, we quickly discover that the statement is ambiguous.
:''Some cat is feared by every mouse''
could mean ''(Some cat is feared) by every mouse'', i.e.
:''For every mouse m, there exists a cat c, such that c is feared by m,''
:\forall m. \, (\, \text(m) \rightarrow \exists c. \, (\text(c) \land \text(m,c)) \, )
in which case the conclusion is trivial.
But it could also mean ''Some cat is (feared by every mouse)'', i.e.
:''There exists one cat c, such that for every mouse m, c is feared by m.''
:\exists c. \, ( \, \text(c) \land \forall m. \, (\text(m) \rightarrow \text(m,c)) \, )
This example illustrates the importance of specifying the scope of quantifiers as ''for all'' and ''there exists''.
==Further reading==

* Patrick Suppes, ''Introduction to Logic'', D. Van Nostrand, 1957, ISBN 978-0-442-08072-3.
* A. G. Hamilton, ''Logic for Mathematicians'', Cambridge University Press, 1978, ISBN 0-521-29291-3.
* Paul Halmos and Steven Givant, ''Logic as Algebra'', MAA, 1998, ISBN 0-88385-327-2.

抄文引用元・出典: フリー百科事典『 ウィキペディア(Wikipedia)
ウィキペディアで「Problem of multiple generality」の詳細全文を読む



スポンサード リンク
翻訳と辞書 : 翻訳のためのインターネットリソース

Copyright(C) kotoba.ne.jp 1997-2016. All Rights Reserved.